Search This Blog

Monday, June 6, 2011

How doctors and public health officials deal with dilemmas

How doctors and public health officials deal with dilemmas


Scientists in the US have investigated the ways in which medical doctors and public health professionals deal with hypothetical dilemmas that require them to decide whether to sacrifice a few for the sake of saving many. Their research extends the kind of dilemma often seen in ethics and philosophy courses, such as the well-known footbridge dilemma, originally suggested by philosophers Philippa Foot and Judith Jarvis Thomson, in which a trolley is about to hurtle into and kill five workers on a railway track. You are on a footbridge spanning the track and can save the workers by pushing a large man next to you off the bridge and into the path of the trolley. The question is, is it morally permissible to kill the one to save the five?
Harvard psychologist Joshua Greene and undergraduate student Katie Ransohoff decided to use more realistic medical dilemmas that real doctors and public health professionals might have to face to test 153 volunteers: 69 of them public health professionals who plan or manage health campaigns and medical resources and 84 medical doctors who actually treat the patients.
The volunteers and 110 controls from unrelated professions were all given the standard dilemmas such as the railway trolley, plus realistic medical dilemmas. One example of the medical dilemmas posed was to decide whether to save a few lives now using expensive treatments or to use the money for thousands of cheap diagnostic tests that could save many patients in the future. Another was whether or not to disconnect life support from a critically ill patient to give several other patients the brief access they needed to the life support machines.
In the trolley dilemma only 12 percent of doctors were willing to kill the one man to save the five workers, and in the life support systems dilemma less than one third of the doctors were willing to sacrifice the critically ill patient to save the others. The results of the medical doctors and volunteers from non-medical professions were not statistically different.
The results for the public health professionals were vastly different, however, with 21 percent willing to kill the man in the trolley dilemma and almost half willing to sacrifice the critically ill man.
Dr. Greene said the results probably reflect the oath doctors take to “do no harm,” and he pointed out that doctors do choose not to sacrifice their patients’ health for the greater good in their overprescribing of antibiotics, which leads to widespread resistance.
Bioethicist Daniel Wilker from the Harvard School of Public Health, who helped design the experiments, said the next stage in the study would be to test public health professionals before and after training. This would enable researchers to tell if the training made people more willing to sacrifice the few for the many, or if people who were so inclined were attracted to working as public health administrators.
The results were reported at the Association for Psychological Science’s annual meeting in Washington D.C.
© 2010 PhysOrg.com
"How doctors and public health officials deal with dilemmas." June 3rd, 2011. http://medicalxpress.com/news/2011-06-doctors-health-dilemmas.html
Comment:
The workers have chosen to be on the tracks and it is their job to look out for trains and get out of the way if one comes.  The large man has chosen not to take any risks, has chosen to stay out of the way of danger, has not volunteered to jump into the path of the trolley to save the men.
The choice would be clearer if we amplify the situation.  Let the people on the track be five stunt men who are doing a show that is about to go wrong.  The large man can not be pushed onto the tracks unless you kill him with a knife first.
 
The amplified case is perfectly clear, the diminutive case is slightly less clear but, even so, your decision based on the choices and risks that people have volunteered to take is clear ~ if you kill the chubby guy, no matter how you try to justify it, you should be tried and convicted of murder.
 
In the medical dilemma all patients are equally responsible or not responsible for their conditions and the choice is one of numbers only, assuming that there was some guarantee that patients would be saved if one patient was allowed to die.  The patient is not an innocent bystander like the chubby guy but has the condition, like the others, which is fatal without treatment.  A snap decision must be made and so nobody could be blamed if the wrong decision was made (because they are not given sufficient time to explore alternatives).
 
In the case of the tests, there is a sufficient intervening period when conditions could change eg more money is made available, doctor's pleas are heeded, medical insurance or other financial conditions could change.  So there is a very real possibility that those sacrificed now might be sacrificed unnecessarily, and nobody wants to be responsible for that and rightly so.
 
The three conditions are different in far too many ways for any trivial comparison of decisions made.  Indeed, they are, if anything, examples of moral blackmail meant to make the person taking the test feel inadequate or amoral regardless of the decision they make.  It's no wonder professionals have lingering contempt for philosopher's absurd and ill-considered questions.
Posted by
Robert Karl Stonjek

No comments:

Post a Comment